100% (1)
page:
1 pages/≈275 words
Sources:
0
Style:
Other
Subject:
Social Sciences
Type:
Coursework
Language:
English (U.S.)
Document:
MS Word
Date:
Total cost:
$ 5.83
Topic:

Annotation on Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument with Historical Illustrations

Coursework Instructions:

In this collaborative reading assignment, you will review and discuss "Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument with Historical Illustrations" by Walzer with your peers using the Perusall tool.

Read the document and annotate it as desired (you may use Perusall to ask questions about the document and gain insight from your peers).  As you peruse this document, consider the following prompt:

  • One question often not considered by military planners is the justness of a conflict.  That seems to be outside the military’s purview but is, in fact, central to our understanding of self, the military, and the place of war in society.
    • As you read through Walzer’s work, what is the utility of considering the concept of a Just War?
    • Do you consider it a dated or unworkable concept or does it still have a place in modern warfare?
    • Does the concept work, as is elsewhere noted in the module, with emerging technologies such as drones and cyber warfare; as in, have we technologically advanced beyond the concept? 

NOTE: It is not required that you answer this prompt in your posts; however, you should consider it as you read and annotate the text.

To earn full credit for this assignment, you must make a minimum of 7-8 thoughtful posts to Perusall.

Note: I do not need a write up. I need you to make comments on the document i sent you. You need to copy and paste the pdf in word in order to make comments unless you can make comments on the pdf directly. I wrote in the instructions that "Read the document and annotate it as desired" and the document must be marked up with your comments and at least 7-8 thoughtful comments/posts that equates something like 300 words total for this assignment. Thank you!

Coursework Sample Content Preview:

The Realist Argument
Student name
Institution
Professor
Course
Date
The Realist Argument
Realism is the issue. The defenders of silent loges claim to have discovered an awful truth: what we conventionally call inhumanity is simply humanity under pressure. War strips away our civilized adornments and reveals our nakedness. They describe that nakedness for us, not without a certain relish: fearful, self-concerned, driven, murderous. They aren't wrong in any simple sense. The words are sometimes descriptive. Paradoxically, the description is often a kind of apology: yes, our soldiers committed atrocities in the course of the battle, but that's what war does to people, that's what war is like. The proverb, all's fair, is invoked in defense of conduct that appears to be unfair. And one urges silence on the law when one is engaged in activities that would otherwise be called unlawful. So there are arguments here that will enter into my own argument: justifications and excuses, references to necessity and duress, that we can recognize as forms of moral discourse and that have or don't have force in particular cases. But there is also a general account of war as a realm of necessity and duress, the purpose of which is to make discourse about particular cases appear to be idle chatter, a mask of noise with which we conceal, even from ourselves, the awful truth. It is that general account that I have to challenge before I can begin my own work, and I want to challenge it at its source and in its most compelling form, as it is put forward by the historian Thucydides and the philosopher Thomas Hobbes. These two men, separated by 2,000 years, are collaborators of a kind, for Hobbes translated Thucydides' History of the Peloponnuidn War and then generali:ied its argument in bis own Leviathan.It is not my purpose here to write a full philosophical response to Thucydides and Hobbes. I wish only to suggest, first by argument and then by example, that the judgment of war and of wartime conduct is a serious enterprise.
Melian Dialogue
The dialogue between the Athenian generals Cleomedes and Tisias and the magistrates of the island state of Melos is one of the high points of Thucydides' History and the climax of his realism. Melos was a Spartan colony, and its people had "therefore refused to be subject, as the rest of the islands were, unto the Athenians; but rested at first neutral; and afterwards, when the Athenians put them to it by wasting of their lands, they entered into open war."'
This is a classic account of aggression, for to commit aggression is simply to "put people to it" as Thucydides describes. But such a description, he seems to say, is merely external; he want, to show us the inner meaning of war. His spokesmen are the two Athenian generals, who demand a parley and then speak as generals have rarely done in military history. I.et us have no fine words about justice, they say. We for our part will not pretend that, having defeated the Persians, our empire is deserved; you must not claim that having done no injury to the Athenian people, you have a right to be let alone. We will talk instead of what is feasible and what is necessary. For this is what war is really like: "they that have odds of power exact as much as they can, and the weak yield to such conditions as they can get."
It is not only the Melians here who bear the burdens of necessity. The Athenians are driven, too; they must expand their empire, Cleomedes and Tisias believe, or lase what they already have. The neutrality of Melos "will be an argument of our weakness, and your hatred of our power, among those we have rule over." It will inspire rebellion throughout the islands, wherever men and women are "offended with the necessity of subjection"-and what subject is not offended, eager for freedom, resentful of his conquerors? When the Athenian generals say that men "will everywhere reign over such as they be too strong for," they are not only describing the desire for glory and command, but also the more narrow necessity of inter-state politics: reign or be subject. If they do not conquer when they can, they only reveal weakness and invite attack; and so, "by a necessity of nature" ( a phrase Hobbes later made his own), they conquer when they can.
The Melians, on the other hand, are too weak to conquer. They face a harsher necessity: yield or be destroyed. "For you have not in hand a match of valor upon equal terms ... but rather a consultation upon your safety ... " The rulers of Melos, however, value freedom above safety: "If you then to retain your command, and your vassals to get loose from you, will undergo the utmost danger: would it not in us, that be already free, be great baseness and cowardice, if we should not encounter anything whatsoever rather than suffer ourselves to be brought into bondage?" Though they know that it will be a "hard matter" to stand against the power and fortune of Athens, "nevertheless we believe that, for fortune, we shall be nothing inferior, as having the gods on our side, because we stand innocent against men unjust." And as for power, they hope for assistance from the Spartans, "who are of necessity obliged, if for no other cause, yet for consanguinity's sake and for their own honor to defend us." But the gods, too, reign where they can, reply the Athenian generals, and consanguinity and honor have nothing to do with necessity. The Spartans will (necessarily) think only of themselves: "most apparently of all men, they hold for honorable that which pleaseth and for just that which profiteth."
So the argument ended. The magistrates refused to surrender; the Athenians laid siege to their city; the Spartans sent no help. Finally, after some months of fighting, in the winter of 416 B.c., Melos was betrayed by several of its citizens. When further re• sistance seemed impossible, the Melians "yielded themselves to the discretion of the Athenians; who slew all the men of military age, made slaves of the women and children; and inhabited the place with a colony sent thither afterwards of 500 men of their own."
The dialogue between the generals and the magistrates is a liter• ary and philosophical construction of Thucydides. The magistrates speak as they well might have done, but their conventional piety and heroism is only a foil to what the classical critic Dionysius calls the "depraved shrewdness" of the Athenian generals.' It is the generals who have often seemed unbelievable. Their words, writes Dionysius, "were appropriate to oriental monarchs ... but unfit to be spoken by Athenians ... "• Perhaps Thucydides means us to notice the unfitness, not so much of the words but of the policies they were used to defend, and thinks we might have missed it had he permitted the gene1als to speak as they probably in fact spoke, weaving "fair pretenses" over their vile actions. We are to understand that Athens is no longer itself. Cleomedes and Tisias do not represent that noble people who fought the Persians in the name of freedom and whose politics and culture, as Dionysius says, "exercised such a humanizing influence on everyday life." They represent instead the imperial decadence of the city state. It is not that they are war criminals in the modem sense; that idea is alien to Thucydides. But they embody a certain loss of ethical balance, of restraint and moderation. Their statesmanship is flawed, and thei1 "realistic" spe,:ches provide an ironic contrast to the blindness and arrogance with which the Athenians only a few months later launched the disastrous expedition to Sicily. The History, on this view, is a tragedy and Athens itself the tragic hero.• Thucydides has given us a morality play in the Greek style. We can glimpse his meaning in Euripides' The Troi•n Women, written in the immediate aftermath of the conquest of Melos and undoubtedly intended to suggest the human significance of slaughter and slave-and to predict a divine retribution:'
How ye are blind Ye treader.; down of cities, yethat cast Temples to desolation, and laywaste Tombs, the untrodden sanctuaries where lie The ancient dead; yourselves so soon to die!
But Thucydides seems in fact to be making a rather different, and a more secular, statement than this quotation suggests, and not about Athens so much as about war itself. He probably did not mean the harshness of the Athenian generals to be taken as a sign of depravity, but rather as a sign of impatience, toughmindedness, honesty---'anything, call necessity cruel and war hellish; but while these statements may be true in their own terms, they do not touch the political realities of the case or help us undentand the Athenian decision.
It is important to stress, however, that Thucydides has told us nothing at all about the Athenian decision. And if we place ourselves, not in the council room at Melos where a cruel policy was being expounded, but in the assembly at Athens where that policy was6nt adopted, the argument of the generals has a very different ring. In the Creek as in the English language, the word necessity "doubles the parts of indispensable and inevitable."' At Melos, Cleomedes and Tisi as mixed the two of these, stressing the last. In the assembly they amid have argued only about the £int, claiming, I suppose, that the destruction of Melos was necessary ( indispensable) for the preservation of the empire. But this claim is rhetorical in two senses. Finl, it evades the moral question of whether the preservation of the empire was itself necessary. There were some Athenians, at least, who had doubts about that, and more who doubted that the empire had to be a uniform system of domination and subjection ( as the policy adopted for Melos suggested). Secondly, it exaggerates the lcnowledge and foresight of the generals. They are not saying with certainty that Athens will fall unless Melos is destroyed; their argument has to do with probabilities and risks.And such arguments are always arguable. Would the destruction of Melos really reduce Athenian risks? Are there alternative policies? What are the lilcely costs of this one? Would it be right? What would other people think of Athens if it were carried out?
Once the debate begins, all sorts of moral and strategic questions are likely to come up. And for the participants in the debate, the outcome is not going to be determined "by a necessity of nature," but by the opinions they hold or come to hold as a result of the arguments they hear and then by the decisions they freely make, individually and collectively. A~erwards, the generals claim that a certain decision was inevitable; and that, presumably, is what Thucydides wants us to believe. But the claim can only be made afterwards, for inevitability here is mediated by a process of political deliberation, and Thucydides could not know what was inevitable until that process had been completed. Judgments of necessity in this sense are always retrospective in character-the work of historians, not historical actoI>.
Now, the moral point of view derives its legitimacy from the penpective of the actor. When we make moral judgments, we try to recapture that penpeclive. We reiterate the decision-making process, or we reheai:se our own future decisions, asking what we would have done ( or what we would do) in similar circumstances. The Athenian generals recogni2e the importance of such questions, for they defend their policy certain "that you likewise, and others that should have the same power which we have, would do the same." But that is a dubious knowledge, especially so once we realize that the "Melian decree" was sharply opposed in the Athenian assembly. Our standpoint is that of citizens debating the decree. ""'1at should we do?
We have no account of the Athenian decision to attack Melos or of the decision ( which may have been taken at the same time) to kill and enslave its people. Plutarch claims that it wasAlcibiades, chief architect of the Sicilian expedition, who was "the principal cause of the slaughter ... having spoken in favor of the decree."' He played the part of Cleon in the debate that Thucydides docs record, that occured some years earlier, over the fate of Mytilene. It is worth glancing back at that earlier argument Mytilene had been an ally of Athens from the time of the Persian War; it was never a subject city in any formal way, but bound by treaty to the Athenian cause. In 428, it rebelled and formed an alliance with the Spartans. After considerable fighting, the city was captured by Athenian forces, and the assembly determined "to put to death ... all the men of Mytilene that were of age, and to make slaves of the women and children: laying to their charge the revolt itself, in that they revolted not being in subjection as others were ... "' But the following day the citizens "felt a kind of repentance ... and began to consider what a great and cruel decree it was, that not the auth~ only, but that the whole city should be destroyed." It is this second debate that Thucydides has recorded, or some part of it, giving us two speeches, that of Ocon upholding the original decree and that of Diodotus urging its revocation. Cleon argues largely in terms of collective guilt and retributive justice; Diodotus offers a critique of the deterrent effects of capital punishment. The assembly a=pts Diodotus' position, convinced apparently that the destruction of Mytilene would not uphold the force of treaties or ensure the stability of the empire. It is the appeal to interesnhat triumphs-as has often been pointed out-though it should be remerobered that the occasion for the appeal was the repentance of the citizens. Moral anxiety, not political calculation, leads them to worry a bout the effectiveness of their decree.
In the debate over Melos, thepositions must have been reversed. Now there was no retributivist argument to make, for the Melians had done Athens no injury. Alcibiades probably talked like Thucydides' generals, though with the all-important diHerence I have already noted. When he told his fellow citizens that the decree was necessary, he didn't mean that it was ordained by the laws that govern the realm of force; he meant merely that it was needed ( in his view) to reduce the risks of rebellion among the subject cities of the Athenian empire. And his opponents probably argued, like the Melians, that the decree was dishonorable and unjust and would more likely excite ,esentment than fear throughout the islands, that Melos did not threaten Athens in any way, and that other policies would serve Athenian interests and Athenian selfesteem. Perhaps they also reminded the citizens of their repentance in the case of Mytilene and urged them once again to avoid the cruelty of massacre and enslavement. How Alcibiades won out, and how close the vote was, we don't know. But there is no reason to think that the decision waspredetermined-and debate of no avail, no more with Metos than with Mytilenc. Stand in imagination in the Athenian assembly, and one can still feel a sense of freedom.
But the realism of the Athenian generals has a further thrust. It is not only a denial of the freedom that makes moral decision possible; it is a denial also of the meaningfulness of moral argument. The second claim is closely related to the first. If we must act in accordance withour interests, driven byour fears of one another, then talk about justice cannot possibly be anything more than talk. It refers to no purposes that we can make our own and to no goals that we can share with others. Thal is why the Athenian generals could have woven "lair pretenses" as easily as the Melian magistrates; in discourse of this sort anything can be said. The words have no clear references, no certain definitions, no logical entailments. They are, as Hobbes writes in Leviathan,"ever used with relation to the person that useth them," and they express that person's appetites and fears and nothing else. It is only "most apparent" in the Spartans, but true for everyone, that "they hold for honorable that which pleaseth them and for just that which profiteth." Or, as Hobbes later explained, the names of the virtues and vices are of 11uncertain signification."'
For one calleth wisdom, what another calleth fear; and one cruelty what another twice; one prodigality, what another magnanimity ... etc. And therefore such names can never be true grounds of any ratiocination.
';Never"-until the sovereigll. who is also the supreme linguistic authority, fixes the meaning of the moral vocabulary; but in the state of war, "never" without qualification, because in that state, by definition, no sovereign rules. In fact, even in civil society, the sovereign does not entirely succeed in bringing certainty into the world of virtue and vice. Hence moral discourse is always suspect, and war is only an extreme case of the anarchy of moral meanings. It is generally true, but especially so in time of violent conflict, that we can undeistand what other people are saying only if we see through their "fair pretenses" and translate moral talkinto the harder currency of interest talk. \Vhen the Melians insist that their cause is just, they arc saying only that they don't want to be subject; and had the generals claimed that Athensdeserved ib empire, they would simply have been expressing the lust for conquest or the fear of overthrow.
This is a powerful argument because it plays upon the common experience of moral disagreement-painful, sustained, exasperating. and endless. For all ib realism, however, it fails to get at the realities of that experience or to explain ib character. We can see this clearly, I think, if we look again at the argument over the Mytilene decree. Hobbes may well have had this debate in mind when he wrote, "and one [ calleth] cruelty what another justice ... " The Athenians repented of their cruelty, writes Thucydides, while Cleon told them that they had not been cruel at all but justly severe. Yet this was in no sense a disagreement over the meaning of words. Had there been no common meanings, there could have been no debate at all. The cruelty of the Athenians consisted in seeking to punish not only the authors of the rebellion but others as well, and Cleon agreed that that would indeed be cruel. He then went on to argue, as he had to do given his position, that in Mytilene there were no "others." "Let not the fault be laid upon a few, and the people absolved. For they have all alike taken arms against us ... "
I cannot pursue the argument further, since Thucydides doesn't, but there is an obvious rejoinder to Cleon, having to do with the status of the women and children of Mytilene. This might involve the deployment of additional moral terms ( innocence, for example); but it would not hang-any more than the argument about cruelty and justice hangs-on idiosyncratic definitions. In fact, definitions are not at issue here, but descriptions and interpretations. The Athenians shared a moral vocabulary, shared it with the people of Mytilene and Melos; and allowing for cultural differences, they share it with us too. They had no difficulty, and we have none, in understanding the claim of the Melian magistrates that the invasion of their island was unjust. It is in applying the agreed-upon words to actual cases that we come to disagree. These disagreemen!s are in part generated and always compounded by antagonistic interest> and ~utthual fears. But theyd dhave other causteS, too which help to explain e comp1ex an ,sparate ways m which men and·women (even when they have similar interes!s and no reason to fear one another) position themselves in the moral world. There are, first of all, serious difficulties of perception and infonnation ( in war and politics generally), and so controversies arise over "the fac!s of the case." There are sharp disparities in the weight we attach even to values we share, as there are in the actions we are ready to condone when these values are threatened. There are contlicting commitrnen!s and oblig,itions that force us into violent antagonism even when we see the point of one another's positions. All this is real enough, and common enough: it makes morality into a world of good-faith quarrels as well as a world of ideology and verbal manipulation.
In any case, the possibilities for manipulation are limited. Whether or not people speak in good faith, they cannot say just anything they please. Moral talk is coercive; one thing leads to another. Perhaps that's why the Athenian generals did not want to begin. A war called unjust is not, to paraphrase Hobbes, a war misliked; it is a war misliked for particular reasons, and anyone making the charge is required to provide particular sorts of evidence. Similarly, if I claim that I am fighting justly, I must also claim that I wasattacked ("put to it," as the Melians were), or threatened with attack, or that I am coming to the aid of a victim of someone else's attack. And each of these claims has its own entailmen!s, leading me deeper and deeper into a world of discourse where, though I can go on talking indefinitely, I am severely constrained in what I can say. I must say this or that, and at many poin!s in a long argument this or that will be true or false. We don't have to translate moral talk into interest talk in order to understand it; morality refers in its own way to the real world.
Let us consider a Hobbist example. In Chapter XXI of Leviathan, Hobbes urges that we make allowance for the "natural timorousness" of mankind. "When armies fight, there is on one side, or both a running away; yet when they do it not out of treachery, but fear, they are not esteemed to do it unjustly, but dishonorably." Now, judgments are called for here: we are to distinguish cowards from traitors. If these are words of "inconstant signification," the task is impossible and absurd. Every traitor would plead natural timorousness, and we would accept the plea or not depending on whether the soldier was a friend or an enemy, an obstacle to our advancement or an ally and supporter. I suppose we sometimes do behave that way, but it is not the case ( nor does Hobbes, when it comes to cases, suppose that it is) that the judgments we make can only be understood in these terms. When we charge a man with treason, we have to tell a very special kind of story about him, and we have to provide concrete evidence that the story is true. If wecall him a traitor when we cannot tell that story, weare not using words inconstantly, weare simply lying.
Strategy and Morality
Morality and justice are talked about in much the same way as military strategy. Strategy is the other language of war, and while. it is commonly said to be free from the difficulties of moral discourse, its use is equally problematic. Though generals agree on the meaning of strategic terms-entrapment, retreat, Banking maneuver, concentration of forces, and so on-they nevertheless disagree about strategically appropriate courses of action. They argue about what ought to be done. After the battle, they disagree about what happened, and if they were defeated, they argue about who was to blame. Strategy, like morality, is a language of justification.• Every confused and cowardly commander describes his hesitations and panics as part of an elaborate plan; the strategic vocabulary is as available to him as it is to a competent commander. But that is not to say that its terms are meaningless. It would be a great triumph
* Hence we can "unmask" str.1.tcgic disco1nse just as Thueydides did with moral discours:e. Imagine that the two Athroian generals, after their dialogue with the Melians, return to their camp to plan the coming battle. The senior in command
11peaks
first: "Don't give me any fine hdk:about the need to concentrate our forces or the importanre of strategic surprise. We'll simply call for a frontalamult; the men willorganiu themselves u best· they can; things are going to be confused any. way, I need a quick victory here, so that I can return to Athens coveredVr'ithglory before the debate on the Sicilian campaign begins. We1l have to accept some risks; but that doesn't matter sincethe riskswillbe yours, not mine. If w,e are beaten, I'll contri,•e to blame you. That's what war is lik:e." \Vhy is strategy the language of han:l.he:idedmen? One seesthroughit so easily ... for the incompetent if they were, for we would then have no way to talk about incompetence. No doubt, "one calleth retreat what another calleth strategic redeployment ... " But we do know the difference between these two, and though the facts of the case may be difficult to collect and interpret, we are nevertheless able to make critical judgments.
Similarly, we can make moral judgments: moral concepts and strategic concepts reflect the real world in the same way. They are not merely normative terms, telling soldiers ( who often don't listen) what to do. They are descriptive terms, and without them we would have no coherent way of talking about war. Here are soldiers moving away from the scene of a battle, marching over the same ground they marched over yesterday, but fewer now, less eager, many without weapons, many wounded: we call this a retreat. Here are soldiers lining up the inhabitants of a peasant village, men, women, and children, and shooting them down: we call this a massacre.
It is only when their substantive content is fairly clear that moral and strategic terms can be used imperatively, and the wisdom they embody expressed in the form of rules. Never refuse quarter to a soldier trying to surrender. Never advance with your flanks unprotected. One might construct out of such commands a moral or a strategic war plan, and then it would be important to notice whether or not the actual conduct of the war conformed to the plan. We can assume that it would not. War is recalcitrant to this sort of theoretical control-a quality it shares with every other human activity, but which it seems to possess to an especially intense degree. In The Charterhouse of Parma, Stendhal provides a description of the battle of Waterloo that is intended to mock the very idea of a strategic plan. It is an account of combat as chaos, therefore not an account at all but a denial, so to speak, that combat is accountable. It should be read alongside some strategic analysis of Waterloo like that of Major General Fuller, who views the battle as an organized series of maneuvers and counter maneuvers.
The strategist is not unaware of confusion and disorder in the. field; nor is he entirely unwilling to see these as aspects of war itself, the natural effects of the stress of battle. But he sees them also as matters of command responsibility, failures of discipline or control. He suggests that strategic imperatives l1ave been ignored; he looks for lessons to be learned.
The moral theorist is in the same position. He too must come to grips with the fact that his rules are often violated or ignoredand with the deeper realization that, to men at war, the rules often don't seem relevant to the extremity of their situation. But however he docs this, he does not surrender his sense of war as a human action, purposive and premeditated, for whose effects someone is responsible. Confronted with the many crimes committed in the course of a war, or with the crime of aggressive war itself, he searches for human agents. Nor is he alone in this search. It is one of the most important features of war, distinguishing it from the other scourges of mankind, that the men and women caught up in it are not only victims, they are also participants. All of us are inclined to hold them responsible for what they do ( though we may recognize the plea of duress in particular eases). Reiterated over time, our arguments and judgments shape what I want to call the moral remity of war-that is, all those experiences of which moral language is descriptive or within which it is necessarily employed.
It is important to stress that the moral reality of war is not fixed by the actual activities of soldiers but by the opinions of mankind. That means, in part, that it is fixed by the activity of philosophers, lawyers, publicists of all sorts. But these people don't work in isolation from the experience of combat, and their views have value only insofar as they give shape and structure to that experience in ways that are plausible to the rest of us. We often say, for example, that in lime of war soldiers and statesmen must make agonizing decisions. The pain is real enough, but it is not one of the natural effects of combat. Agony is not like Hobbist fear; it is entirely the product of our moral views, and it is common in war only insofar as those views are common. It was not some unusual Athenian who "repented" of the decision to kill the men of Mytilene, but the citizens generally. They repented, and they were able to understand one another's repentance, bec...
Updated on
Get the Whole Paper!
Not exactly what you need?
Do you need a custom essay? Order right now:

👀 Other Visitors are Viewing These APA Essay Samples:

Sign In
Not register? Register Now!